### TL;DR This paper explores three behavioral economic concepts...
Other papers by the authors that you can find annotated Fermat's Li...
***loss aversion***: the disutility of giving up an object is great...
In a nutshell people tend to value an item they own more highly tha...
***"The experiment was replicated several times, always with simila...
This graph shows two indifference curves that cross, which isn’t su...
Even when people are randomly given an item (like a pen) only momen...
Given a choice **people tend to stick with the default or current o...
**Losing feels more painful than winning. ** People feel losses ...
**People perceive losses as less fair than missed gains, even if th...
The authors argue that **these behavioral patterns are not just exc...
Journal of
Economic PerspectivesVolume
5, Number 1Winter 1991Pages 193–206
Anomalies
The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion,
and Status Quo Bias
Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch,
and Richard H. Thaler
Economics can be distinguished from other social sciences by the belief that
most (all?) behavior can be explained by assuming that agents have stable,
well-defined preferences and make rational choices consistent with those
pref-
erences in markets that (eventually) clear. An empirical result qualifies as an
anomaly if it is difficult to "rationalize," or if implausible assumptions are
necessary to explain it within the paradigm. This column presents a series of
such anomalies. Readers are invited to suggest topics for future columns by
sending a note with some reference to (or better yet copies of) the relevant
research. Comments on anomalies printed here are also welcome. The address
is:
Richard Thaler, c/o Journal of Economic Perspectives, Johnson Graduate
School of Management, Malott Hall, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY 14853.
After this issue, the "Anomalies" column will no longer appear in every
issue and instead will appear occasionally, when a pressing anomaly crosses
Dick Thaler's desk. However, suggestions for new columns and comments on
old ones are still welcome. Thaler would like to quash one rumor before it gets
started, namely that he is cutting back because he has run out of anomalies. Au
contraire,
it is the dilemma of choosing which juicy anomaly to discuss that takes
so much time.
Daniel Kahneman is Professor of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley,
California. Jack L. Knetsch is Professor of Economics and Natural Resources Manage-
ment, Simon Eraser University, Burnaby, British Columbia, Canada. Richard H. Thaler
is Henrietta Johnson Louis Professor of Economics, Johnson School of Management,
Cornell University, Ithaca, New York.
194 Journal of Economic Perspectives
Introduction
A wine-loving economist we know purchased some nice Bordeaux wines
years ago at low prices. The wines have greatly appreciated in value, so that a
bottle that cost only $10 when purchased would now fetch $200 at auction. This
economist now drinks some of this wine occasionally, but would neither be
willing to sell the wine at the auction price nor buy an additional bottle at that
price.
Thaler (1980) called this pattern—the fact that people often demand much
more to give up an object than they would be willing to pay to acquire it—the
endowment
effect.
The example also illustrates what Samuelson and Zeckhauser
(1988) call a status quo bias, a preference for the current state that biases the
economist against both buying and selling his wine. These anomalies are a
manifestation of an asymmetry of value that Kahneman and Tversky (1984) call
loss aversion—the disutility of giving up an object is greater that the utility
associated with acquiring it. This column documents the evidence supporting
endowment effects and status quo biases, and discusses their relation to loss
aversion.
The Endowment Effect
An early laboratory demonstration of the endowment effect was offered by
Knetsch and Sinden (1984). The participants in this study were endowed with
either a lottery ticket or with $2.00. Some time later, each subject was offered
an opportunity to trade the lottery ticket for the money, or vice versa. Very few
subjects chose to switch. Those who were given lottery tickets seemed to like
them better than those who were given money.
This demonstration and other similar ones (Knetsch, 1989), while striking,
did not settle the matter. Some economists felt that the behavior would
disappear if subjects were exposed to a market environment with ample
learning opportunities. For example, Knez, Smith and Williams (1985) argued
that the discrepancy between buying and selling prices might be produced by
the thoughtless application of normally sensible bargaining habits, namely
understating one's true willingness to pay (WTP) and overstating the minimum
acceptable price at which one would sell (willingness to accept or WTA).
Coursey, Hovis, and Schultze (1987) reported that the discrepancy between
WTP and WTA diminished with experience in a market setting (although it was
probably not eliminated, see Knetsch and Sinden, 1987). To clarify the issue,
Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler (1990) ran a new series of experiments to
determine whether the endowment effect survives when subjects face market
discipline and have a chance to learn. We will report just two experiments from
that series.
Daniel
Kahneman,
Jack L. Knetsch, and Richard H. Thaler 195
In the first experiment, students in an advanced undergraduate economics
class at Cornell University participated in a series of markets. The objects
traded in the first three markets were 'induced value tokens.' In such markets
all subjects are told how much a token is worth to them, with the amounts
varying across subjects. Half the subjects were made owners of tokens, the other
half were not. In this way, supply and demand curves for tokens are created.
Subjects alternated between the buyer and seller role in the three successive
markets, and were assigned a different individual redemption value in each
trial. Experimenters collected the forms from all participants after each market
period, and immediately calculated and announced the market-clearing price
and the number of trades. Three buyers and three sellers were selected at
random after each of the induced markets and were paid off according to the
preferences stated on their forms and the market clearing price for that period.
These markets contained no grist for the anomaly mill. On each trial, the
market clearing price was exactly equal to the intersection of the induced
supply and demand curves, and the volume of trade was within one unit of the
predicted quantity. These results demonstrate that the subjects understood the
task, and that the market mechanism used did not impose high transactions
costs.
Immediately after the three induced value markets, subjects on alternating
seats were given Cornell coffee mugs, which sell for $6.00 each at the book-
store. The experimenter asked all participants to examine a mug, either their
own or their neighbor's. The experimenter then informed the subjects that
four markets for mugs would be conducted using the same procedures as the
prior induced markets with two exceptions: (1) One of the four market trials
would subsequently be selected at random and only the trades made on this
trial would be executed. (2) On the binding market trial, all trades would be
implemented, unlike the subset implemented in the induced value markets.
The initial assignment of buyer and seller roles was maintained for all four
trading periods. The clearing price and the number of trades were announced
after each period. The market that "counted" was indicated after the fourth
period, and transactions were executed immediately—all sellers who had indi-
cated that they would give up their mug at the market clearing price ex-
changed their mugs for cash, and successful buyers paid this same price and
received their mug. This design was used to permit learning to take place over
successive trials and yet make each trial potentially binding. The same proce-
dure was then followed for four more successive markets using boxed ball-point
pens with a visible bookstore price tag of $3.98, which were distributed to the
subjects who had been buyers in the mug markets.
What does economic theory predict will happen in these markets for mugs
and pens? Since transactions costs have been shown to be insignificant in the
induced value markets, and income effects are trivial, a clear prediction is
available: When the market clears, the objects will be owned by those subjects
who value them most. Call the half of the subjects who like mugs the most
796 Journal of Economic Perspectives
"mug lovers" and the half who like mugs least "mug haters." Then, since the
mugs were assigned at random, on average half of the mug lovers will be given
a mug, and half will not. This implies that in the market, half of the mugs
should trade, with mug haters selling to mug lovers.
The 50 percent predicted volume of trade did not materialize. There were
22 mugs and pens distributed so the predicted number of trades was 11. In the
four mug markets the number of trades was 4, 1, 2, and 2 respectively. In
the pen markets the number of trades was either 4 or 5. In neither market was
there any evidence of a trend over the four trials. The reason for the low
volume of trade is revealed by the reservation prices of buyers and sellers. For
mugs,
the median owner was unwilling to sell for less than $5.25, while the
median buyer was unwilling to pay more than $2.25-$2.75. The market price
varied between $4.25 and $4.75. In the market for pens the ratio of selling to
buying prices was also about 2. The experiment was replicated several times,
always with similar results: median selling prices are about twice median buying
prices and volume is less than half of that expected.
Another experiment from this series allows us to investigate whether the
low volume of trading is produced by a reluctance to buy or a reluctance to sell.
In this experiment, 77 students at Simon Fraser University were randomly
assigned to three conditions. One group, the Sellers, were given SFU coffee
mugs and were asked whether they would be willing to sell the mugs at each of
a series of prices ranging from $0.25 to $9.25. A second group of Buyers were
asked whether they would be willing to buy a mug at the same set of prices.
The third group, called Choosers, were not given a mug but were asked to
choose, for each of the prices, between receiving a mug or that amount of
money.
Notice that the Sellers and the Choosers are in objectively identical situa-
tions,
deciding at each price between the mug and that amount of money.
Nevertheless, the Choosers behaved more like Buyers than like Sellers. The
median reservation prices were: Sellers, $7.12; Choosers, $3.12; Buyers, $2.87.
This suggests that the low volume of trade is produced mainly by owner's
reluctance to part with their endowment, rather than by buyers' unwillingness
to part with their cash. This experiment also eliminates the trivial income effect
present in the first experiment, since the Sellers and Choosers are in the same
economic situation.
One of the first lessons in microeconomics is that two indifference curves
can never intersect. This result depends on the implicit assumption that
indifference curves are reversible. That is, if an individual owns x and is
indifferent between keeping it and trading it for y, then when owning y the
individual should be indifferent about trading it for x. If loss aversion is
present, however, this reversibility will no longer hold. Knetsch (1990) has
demonstrated this point experimentally. One group of subjects received 5
medium priced ball point pens, while another group of subjects received $4.50.
They were then made a series of offers which they could accept or reject. The
offers were designed to identify an indifference curve. For example, someone
Anomalies 197
Figure 1
Crossing indifference curves
who had been given the pens would be asked if she would give up one of the
pens for a dollar. One of the accepted offers (including the original endow-
ment) was selected at random at the end of the experiment to determine the
subject's payment. By plotting the line between accepted and rejected offers,
Knetsch was able to infer an indifference curve for each subject. Then he
plotted the average indifference curve for each of the two groups (those who
started with pens and those who started with money). These plots are shown in
Figure 1. The curves are quite different: the pens were worth more money to
those subjects who started with pens than to those who started with money. As
a result, the curves intersect.
1
What produces these "instant endowment effects"? Do subjects who receive
a gift actually value it more than others who do not receive it? A recent study by
Loewenstein and Kahneman (1991) investigated this issue. Half the students in
a class (N = 63) were given pens, the others were given a token redeemable for
an unspecified gift. All participants were then asked to rank the attractiveness
of six gifts under consideration as prizes in subsequent experiments. Finally, all
the subjects were then given a choice between a pen and two chocolate bars. As
in previous experiments, there was a pronounced endowment effect. The pen
was preferred by 56 percent of those endowed with it, but only 24 percent of
the other subjects chose a pen. However, when making the attractiveness
ratings, the subjects endowed with pens did not rate them as more attractive.
This suggests that the main effect of endowment is not to enhance the appeal of
the good one owns, only the pain of giving it up.
Status Quo Bias
One implication of loss aversion is that individuals have a strong tendency
to remain at the status quo, because the disadvantages of leaving it loom larger
1
These curves were obtained from different individuals. Because subjects were randomly assigned
to the two endowment groups, however, it is reasonable to attribute crossing indifference curves to
the representative individual.
198 Journal of Economic Perspectives
than advantages. Samuelson and Zeckhauser (1988) have demonstrated this
effect, which they term the status quo bias. In one experiment, some subjects
were given a hypothetical choice task, such as the following, in a 'neutral'
version in which no status quo is defined: "You are a serious reader of the
financial pages but until recently have had few funds to invest. That is when
you inherited a large sum of money from your great-uncle. You are consider-
ing different portfolios. Your choices are to invest in: a moderate-risk company,
a high risk company, treasury bills, municipal bonds."
Other subjects were presented with the same problem but with one of the
options designated as the status quo. In this case, after the same opening
sentence the passage continues: "... That is when you inherited a portfolio of
cash and securities from your great-uncle. A significant portion of this portfolio
is invested in a moderate risk company ... (The tax and broker commission
consequences of any change are insignificant.)"
Many different scenarios were investigated, all using the same basic experi-
mental design. Aggregating across all the different questions, Samuelson and
Zeckhauser are then able to estimate the probability that an option will be
selected when it is the status quo or when it is competing as an alternative to
the status quo as a function of how often it is selected in the neutral setting.
Their results implied that an alternative became significantly more popular
when it was designated as the status quo. Also, the advantage of the status quo
increases with the number of alternatives.
A test of status quo bias in a field setting was performed by Hartman,
Doane, and Woo (forthcoming) using a survey of California electric power
consumers. The consumers were asked about their preferences regarding
service reliability and rates. They were told that their answers would help
determine company policy in the future. The respondents fell into two groups,
one with much more reliable service than the other. Each group was asked to
state a preference among six combinations of service reliabilities and rates, with
one of the combinations designated as the status quo. The results demonstrated
a pronounced status quo bias. In the high reliability group, 60.2 percent
selected their status quo as their first choice, while only 5.7 percent expressed a
preference for the low reliability option currently being experienced by the
other group, though it came with a 30 percent reduction in rates. The low
reliability group, however, quite liked their status quo, 58.3 percent of them
ranking it first. Only 5.8 percent of this group selected the high reliability
option at a proposed 30 percent increase in rates.
2
2
Differences in income and electricity consumption between the two groups were minor and did
not appear to significantly influence the results. Could the results be explained by either learning of
habituation? That is, might the low reliability group have learned to cope with frequent outages, or
found out that candlelight dinners are romantic? This cannot be ruled out, but it should be stressed
that no similar explanation can be used for the mug experiments or the surveys conducted by
Samuelson and Zeckhauser, so at least some of the effects observed are attributable to a pure status
quo bias.
Daniel
Kahneman,
Jack L. Knetsch, and Richard H. Thaler 199
A large-scale experiment on status quo bias is now being conducted
(inadvertently) by the states of New Jersey and Pennsylvania. Both states now
offer a choice between two types of automobile insurance: a cheaper policy that
restricts the right to sue, and a more expensive one that maintains the
unrestricted right. Motorists in New Jersey are offered the cheaper policy as the
default option, with an opportunity to acquire an unrestricted right to sue at a
higher price. Since this option was made available in 1988, 83 percent of the
drivers have elected the default option. In Pennsylvania's 1990 law, however,
the default option is the expensive policy, with an opportunity to opt for the
cheaper kind. The potential effect of this legislative framing manipulation was
studied by Hershey, Johnson, Meszaros, and Robinson (1990). They asked two
groups to choose between alternative policies. One group was presented with
the New Jersey plan while the other was presented with the Pennsylvania plan.
Of those subjects offered the New Jersey plan, only 23 percent elected to buy
the right to sue whereas 53 percent of the subjects offered the Pennsylvania
plan retained that right. On the basis of this research, the authors predict that
more Pennsylvanians will elect the right to sue than New Jerseyans. Time will
tell.
One final example of a presumed status quo bias comes courtesy of the
JEP
staff.
Among Carl Shapiro's comments on this column was this gem: "You
may be interested to know that when the AEA was considering letting members
elect to drop one of the three Association journals and get a credit, prominent
economists involved in that decision clearly took the view that fewer members
would choose to drop a journal if the default was presented as all three journals
(rather than the default being 2 journals with an extra charge for getting all
three).
We're talking economists here."
Loss Aversion
These observations, and many others, can be explained by a notion of loss
aversion. A central conclusion of the study of risky choice has been that such
choices are best explained by assuming that the significant carriers of utility are
not states of wealth or welfare, but changes relative to a neutral reference point.
Another central result is that changes that make things worse (losses) loom
larger than improvements or gains. The choice data imply an abrupt change of
the slope of the value function at the origin. The existing evidence suggests that
the ratio of the slopes of the value function in two domains, for small or
moderate gains and losses of money, is about 2: 1 (Tversky and Kahneman,
1991).
A schematic value function is shown in Figure 2.
The natural extension of this idea to riskless choice is that the attributes of
options in trades and other transactions are also evaluated as gains and losses
relative to a neutral reference point. The approach is illustrated in Figure 3.
Decision makers have a choice between state A, where they have more of good
200 Journal of
Economic
Perspectives
Figure 2
A typical value function
Y and less of good X, and state D, where they have more of good X and less of
good Y. Four different reference points are indicated in the Figure. The
individual faces a positive choice between two gains if the reference point is C, a
negative choice between two losses if the reference point is B, and two different
exchanges if the references are A or D, respectively. For example, if good Y is a
mug and good X is money, the reference points for the sellers and the choosers
in the mugs experiment are A and C. Loss aversion implies that the difference
between the states of having a mug and not having one is larger from A than
from C, which explains the different monetary values that subjects attach to the
mug in these conditions.
3
For a formal treatment that generalizes consumer
theory by introducing the notions of reference and loss aversion, see Tversky
and Kahneman (1991).
In general, a given difference between two options will have greater impact
if it is viewed as a difference between two disadvantages than if it is viewed as a
difference between two advantages. The status quo bias is a natural conse-
quence of this asymmetry: the disadvantages of a change loom larger than its
advantages. However, the differential weighting of advantages and disadvan-
tages can be demonstrated even when the retention of the status quo is not an
option. For an example, consider the following question (from Tversky and
Kahneman, 1991):
Imagine that as part of your professional training you were assigned to a
part-time job. The training is now ending and you must look for employ-
3
Loss
aversion does not affect all transactions. In a normal commercial transaction, the seller does
not
suffer a loss when trading a good. Furthermore, the evidence indicates that buyers do not value
the
money spent on normal purchases as a
loss,
so long as the price of the good is not thought to be
unusually
high. Loss aversion is expected to primarily affect owners of goods that had been bought
for
use rather than for eventual resale.
Anomalies
201
Figure
3
Multiple reference points for the choice between
A and D
ment. You consider two possibilities. They are like your training job in
most respects except for the amount of social contact and the convenience
of commuting to and from work. To compare the two jobs to each other
and to the present one you have made up the following table:
Job
Present job
Job A
Job D
Contact with others
isolated for long stretches
limited contact with others
moderately sociable
Commute Time
10 min.
20 min.
60 min.
The options A and D are evaluated from a reference job which is better on
commute time and worse on personal contact (a point like A' in Figure 3).
Another version of the problem presented the same options, but the reference
job involved "much pleasant social interaction and 80 minutes of daily commut-
ing time," which corresponds to the point D . The proportion of subjects
choosing job A was 70 percent in the first version, 33 percent in the second.
Subjects are more sensitive to the dimension in which they are losing relative to
their reference point.
Some asymmetries between buying and selling prices are much too large to
be explained by garden-variety loss aversion. For example, Thaler (1980) told
subjects that they had been exposed to a rare fatal disease and that they now
face a .001 chance of painless death within two weeks. They must decide how
much they would be willing to pay for a vaccine, to be purchased immediately.
The same subjects were also asked for the compensation they would demand to
202 Journal of Economic Perspectives
participate in a medical experiment in which they face a .001 chance of a quick
and painless death. For most subjects the two prices differed by more than an
order of magnitude.
A study by Viscusi, Magat and Huber (1987) documented a similar effect in
a more realistic setting. Their respondents were recruited at a shopping mall
and hardware store. The respondents were shown a can of fictitious insecticide,
and were asked to examine it for their use. The current price of the can was
said to be $10. Respondents were informed that all insecticide can cause
injuries if misused, including inhalation and skin poisoning (in households with
young children, child poisoning replaced skin poisoning). The current risk
level was said to be 15 injuries of each type per 10,000 bottles sold. Respon-
dents were asked to state their willingness-to-pay (WTP) to eliminate or reduce
the risks. In households without children, the mean WTP to eliminate both
risks was $3.78. The respondents were also asked to state the price reduction
they would require to accept an increase of
1/10,000
in each of the two risks.
The results were dramatic: 77 percent of respondents in this condition said
they would refuse to buy the product at any positive price.
The striking difference between WTA and WTP in these studies probably
reflects the large difference in the responsibility costs associated with voluntary
assumption of additional risk, in contrast to a mere failure to reduce or
eliminate existing risk. The asymmetry between omission and commission is
familiar in legal doctrine, and its impact on judgments of responsibility has
been confirmed by psychological research (Ritov and Baron, forthcoming). The
asymmetry affects both blame and regret after a mishap, and the anticipation of
blame and regret, in turn, could affect behavior.
A moral attitude is involved in another situation where huge discrepancies
between buying and selling prices have been observed, the evaluation of
environmental amenities in cost benefit analyses. Suppose some corporation
offers to buy the Grand Canyon and make it into a water park complete with
the world's largest water slide. How do we know whether the benefits of this
idea exceed its costs? As usual there are two ways to ask the question, depend-
ing on what is the status quo. If there is no theme park in the status quo, then
people can be asked the minimum amount of money they would accept to
agree to add one (WTA). Alternatively, if the corporation currently owns the
right, people could be asked how much they would be willing to pay to buy it
back and prevent the theme park from being built (WTP). Several surveys have
been conducted where the researchers asked both types of questions for such
things as clean air and well-maintained public parks. Most studies find that the
WTA responses greatly exceed the WTP answers (Cummings, Brookshire, and
Schulze, 1986). The difference in typical responses actually does not tell the
entire story. As two close observers of this literature note (Mitchell and Carson,
1989,
p. 34): "Studies using WTA questions have consistently received a large
number of protest answers, such as 'I refuse to sell' or 'I want an extremely
large or infinite amount of compensation for agreeing to this,' and have
Daniel
Kahneman,
Jack L. Knetsch, and Richard H. Thaler 203
frequently experienced protest rates [outright refusals to answer the question]
of 50 percent or more." These extreme responses reflect the feelings of outrage
often seen when communities are faced with the prospect of accepting a new
risk such as a nuclear power plant or waste disposal facility (Kunreuther,
Easterling, Desvousges, and Slovic, forthcoming). Offers of compensation to
proposed communities often do not help as they are typically perceived as
bribes.
4
Judgments of Fairness and Justice
An implication of the endowment effect is that people treat opportunity
costs differently than "out-of-pocket" costs. Foregone gains are less painful than
perceived losses. This perception is strongly manifested in people's judgments
about fair behavior. Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler (1986) present survey
evidence supporting this proposition. Samples of the residents of Toronto and
Vancouver were asked a series of questions over the telephone about whether
they thought a particular economic action was "fair." In some cases, alternative
versions of the same question were presented to different groups of respon-
dents.
For each question, respondents were asked to judge whether the action
was completely fair, acceptable, somewhat unfair, or very unfair. In reporting
the results the first two categories were combined and called "acceptable" and
the last two combined and called "unfair." Perceptions of fairness strongly
depended on whether the question was framed as a reduction in a gain or an
actual loss. For example:
Question 1a. A shortage has developed for a popular model of
automobile, and customers must now wait two months for delivery. A
dealer has been selling these cars at list price. Now the dealer prices this
model at $200 above list price.
N = 130 Acceptable 29 percent Unfair 71 percent
Question 1b. A shortage has developed for a popular model of
automobile, and customers must now wait two months for delivery. A
dealer has been selling these cars at a discount of $200 below list price.
Now the dealer sells this model only at list price.
N = 123 Acceptable 58 percent Unfair 42 percent
4
This is a situation in which people loudly say one thing and the theory asserts another. It is of
interest that the practitioners of contingent valuation elected to listen to the theory, rather than to
the respondents (Cummings, Brookshire and Schulze, 1986). The accepted procedure uses WTP
questions to assess value even in a context of compensation, relying on the theoretical argument
that WTP and WTA should not be far apart when income effects are small.
204 Journal of Economic Perspectives
Imposing a surcharge (which is likely to be judged a loss) is considered
more unfair than eliminating a discount (a reduction of a gain). This distinction
explains why firms that charge cash customers one price and credit card
customers a higher price always refer to the cash price as a discount rather than
to the credit card price as a surcharge (Thaler, 1980).
The different intensity of responses to losses and to foregone gains may
help explain why it is easier to cut real wages during inflationary periods:
Question 2a. A company is making a small profit. It is located in a
community experiencing a recession with substantial unemployment but
no inflation. The company decides to decrease wages and salaries 7
percent this year.
N = 125 Acceptable 37 percent Unfair 63 percent
Question 2b. A company is making a small profit. It is located in a
community experiencing a recession with substantial unemployment and
inflation of 12 percent. The company decides to increase salaries only 5
percent this year.
N = 129 Acceptable 78 percent Unfair 22 percent
In this case a 7 percent cut in real wages is judged reasonably fair when it
is framed as a nominal wage increase, but quite unfair when it is posed as a
nominal wage cut.
The attitudes of the lay public about fairness, which are represented in
their answers to these fairness questions, also pervade the decisions made by
judges in many fields of the law. Supreme Court Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes
(1897) put the principle this way: "It is in the nature of a man's mind. A thing
which you enjoyed and used as your own for a long time, whether property or
opinion, takes root in your being and cannot be torn away without your
resenting the act and trying to defend
yourself,
however you came by it. The
law can ask no better justification than the deepest instincts of man."
Cohen and Knetsch (1990) showed that this principle, embodied in the old
expression that "possession is nine tenths of the law," is reflected in many
judicial opinions. For example, in tort law judges make the distinction between
"loss by way of expenditure and failure to make gain." In one case, several
bales fell from the defendant's truck and hit a utility pole, cutting off power to
the plaintiff's plant. The plaintiff was able to recover wages paid to employees
which were considered "positive outlays" but could not recover lost profits
which were merely "negative losses consisting of a mere deprivation of an
opportunity to earn an income" (p. 18). A similar distinction is made in contract
law. A party that breaches a contract is more likely to be held to the original
terms if the action is taken to make an unforeseen gain than if it is taken to
avoid a loss.
Anomalies 205
Commentary
It is in the nature of economic anomalies that they violate standard theory.
The next question is what to do about it. In many cases there is no obvious way
to amend the theory to fit the facts, either because too little is known, or
because the changes would greatly increase the complexity of the theory and
reduce its predictive yield. The anomalies that we have described under the
labels of the endowment effect, the status quo bias and loss aversion may be an
exceptional case, where the needed amendments in the theory are both obvious
and tractable.
The amendments are not trivial: the important notion of a stable prefer-
ence order must be abandoned in favor of a preference order that depends on
the current reference level. A revised version of preference theory would assign
a special role to the status quo, giving up some standard assumptions of
stability, symmetry and reversibility which the data have shown to be false. But
the task is manageable. The generalization of preference theory to indifference
curves that are indexed to reference level is straightforward (Tversky and
Kahneman, 1991). The factors that determine the reference point in the
evaluations of outcomes are reasonably well understood: the role of the status
quo,
and of entitlements and expectations are sufficiently well established to
allow these factors to be used in locating the relevant reference levels for
particular analyses.
As Samuelson and Zeckhauser noted, rational models that ignore the status
quo tend to predict "greater instability than is observed in the world" (p. 47).
We have added the claim that models that ignore loss aversion predict more
symmetry and reversibility than are observed in the world, ignoring potentially
large differences in the magnitude of responses to gains and to losses. Re-
sponses to increases and to decreases in price, for example, might not always be
mirror images of each other. The possibility of loss aversion effects suggests,
more generally, that treatments of responses to changes in economic variables
should routinely separate the cases of favorable and unfavorable changes.
Introducing such distinctions could improve the precision of predictions at a
tolerable price in increased complexity.
After more than a decade of research on this topic we have become
convinced that the endowment effect, status quo bias, and the aversion to losses
are both robust and important. Then again, we admit that the idea is now part
of our endowment, and we are naturally keener to retain it than others might
be to acquire it.
The authors wish to acknowledge financial support from Fisheries and Oceans
Canada, the Ontario Ministry of the Environment, the Russell Sage Foundation, and
Concord Capital Management.
206 Journal
of
Economic Perspectives
References
Cohen, David,
and
Jack
L.
Knetsch "Judi-
cial Choice
and
Disparities Between Measures
of Economic Values," Simon Fraser University
Working Paper,
1990.
Goursey,
Don L.,
John
L.
Hovis,
and
William
D.
Schulze,
"The
Disparity Between
Willingness
to
Accept
and
Willingness
to Pay
Measures
of
Value,"
The
Quarterly
Journal
of
Economics,
1987, 102,
679–90.
Gummings, Ronald
G.,
David
S.
Brookshire,
and
William
D.
Schulze,
eds.,
Valuing Environmental Goods. Totowa,
NJ:
Rowman
and
Allanheld,
1986.
Hartman, Raymond, Michael
J.
Doane,
and
Chi-Keung
Woo,
"Consumer Rationality
and
the Status Quo,"
Quarterly
Journal
of
Economics,
forthcoming.
Hershey, John, Eric Johnson, Jacqueline
Meszaros,
and
Matthew Robinson, "What
Is
the Right
to Sue
Worth?" Wharton School,
University
of
Pennsylvania, June
1990.
Holmes, Oliver Wendell, "The Path
of the
Law,"
Harvard
Law
Review,
1897, 10, 457–478.
Kahneman, Daniel, Jack
L.
Knetsch,
and
Richard Thaler, "Fairness
As a
Constraint
on
Profit Seeking: Entitlements
in the
Market,"
American Economic
Review,
1986, 76,
728–41.
Kahneman, Daniel, Jack
L.
Knetsch,
and
Richard Thaler, "Experimental Tests
of the
Endowment Effect
and the
Coase Theorem,"
Journal
of
Political
Economy,
December
1990,
98, 1325–1348.
Kahneman, Daniel,
and
Amos Tversky,
"Choices, Values
and
Frames,"
American
Psy-
chologist,
April
1984, 39,
341–350.
Knetsch, Jack
L., "The
Endowment Effect
and Evidence
of
Nonreversible Indifference
Curves,"
American Economic
Review,
1989, 79,
1277–1284.
Knetsch, Jack
L.,
"Derived Indifference
Curves," working paper, Simon Fraser
Uni-
versity,
1990.
Knetsch, Jack
L., and J. A.
Sinden,
"Wil-
lingness
to Pay and
Compensation
De-
manded: Experimental Evidence
of an
Unex-
pected Disparity
in
Measures
of
Value," Quar-
terly Journal
of
Economics,
August
1984, 99,
507–521.
Knetsch, Jack
L., and J. A.
Sinden,
"The
Persistence
of
Evaluation Disparities," Quar-
terly
Journal
of
Economics,
1987, 102,
691–695.
Knez, Peter, Vernon Smith,
and
Arlington
W. Williams, "Individual Rationality, Market
Rationality,
and
Value Estimation," American
Economic
Review,
May 1985, 75,
397–402.
Kunreuther, Howard, Douglas Easterling,
William Desvousges,
and
Paul Slovic, "Public
Attitudes Toward Citing
a
High Level Nuclear
Waste Depository
in
Nevada," Risk Analysis,
forthcoming.
Lowenstein, George, and Daniel
Kahneman, "Explaining
the
Endowment
Ef-
fect," working paper, Department
of
Social
and Decision Sciences, Carnegie Mellon
Uni-
versity,
1991.
Mitchell, Robert
C., and R. T.
Carson,
Us-
ing
Surveys
to
Value
Public
Goods.
Washington,
D.C.: Resources
for the
Future,
1989.
Ritov, Rita,
and
Jonathan Baron, "Status-
quo
and
Omission Biases," Journal
of
Risk
and
Uncertainty,
forthcoming.
Samuelson, William,
and
Richard
Zeckhauser, "Status
Quo
Bias
in
Decision
Making," Journal
of
Risk
and
Uncertainty,
1988,
1,
7–59.
Thaler, Richard, "Toward
a
Positive
The-
ory
of
Consumer Choice," Journal
of
Economic
Behavior
and
Organization,
1980, 1,
39–60.
Tversky, Amos,
and
Daniel Kahneman,
"Loss Aversion
and
Riskless Choice:
A
Refer-
ence Dependent Model,"
Quarterly
Journal
of
Economics,
1991.
Viscusi,
W.
Kip, Wesley
A.
Magat, and Joel
Huber,
"An
Investigation
of the
Rationality
of
Consumer Valuations
of
Multiple Health
Risks,"
RAND Journal
of
Economics,
1987, 18,
465–79.

Discussion

In a nutshell people tend to value an item they own more highly than an identical item they do not own. This graph shows two indifference curves that cross, which isn’t supposed to happen if a person's choices are consistent. Each curve represents combinations of pens and dollars that give the same level of satisfaction to the consumer. If the curves cross, it means the same combination of goods is both equally satisfying and not equally satisfying, which is a contradiction. Other papers by the authors that you can find annotated Fermat's Library: - [Mental Accounting and Consumer Choice - Richard Thaler](https://fermatslibrary.com/s/mental-accounting-and-consumer-choice) - [Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases - Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman](https://fermatslibrary.com/s/judgment-under-uncertainty-heuristics-and-biases) - [Prospect Theory - Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky](https://fermatslibrary.com/s/prospect-theory-an-analysis-of-decision-under-risk) ***loss aversion***: the disutility of giving up an object is greater that the utility associated with acquiring that same object. **Losing feels more painful than winning. ** People feel losses more strongly than equivalent gains, leading to decisions that are biased toward avoiding loss even when it’s not rational. This helps explain why people resist trades or changes that would otherwise benefit them. The concept is central to understanding many deviations from standard economic behavior. ***"The experiment was replicated several times, always with similar results: median selling prices are about twice median buying prices and volume is less than half of that expected."*** Even when people are randomly given an item (like a pen) only moments before, they become significantly more likely to choose it over other alternatives. The observations here reinforce the idea that ownership instantly changes preferences where the pain of losing something outweighs any rational evaluation of its value. ### TL;DR This paper explores three behavioral economic concepts: the endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. These concepts challenge the standard economic assumption that people have stable and rational preferences. Through a series of clever experiments and real-world examples, the authors show that: - individuals value items more highly simply because they own them (endowment effect) - feel the pain of losses more acutely than the pleasure of equivalent gains (loss aversion) - and tend to stick with default options even when better alternatives exist (status quo bias). These behaviors persist even in settings that should encourage rational behavior, suggesting that they are deep-rooted tendencies. These concepts are especially important for understanding how people respond to losses and defaults, especially in a world filled with nudges, dark patterns, and subscription traps. The ideas in this paper continue to shape behavioral economics, influencing everything from retirement plan participation to healthcare decisions and digital product design. It’s a must-read if you want to understand why people often act in ways that defy classical economic logic. The authors argue that **these behavioral patterns are not just exceptions but core features of decision-making.** Standard economic models need to adapt by recognizing reference points and loss sensitivity. Doing so can make predictions more accurate and useful in the real world. Given a choice **people tend to stick with the default or current option, even when better alternatives exist.** This bias gets stronger as the number of options increases. It’s another example of loss aversion, where changing feels riskier than staying the same. Given a choice, people tend to stick with the default or current option even when better alternatives exist. This bias gets stronger as the number of options increases. It’s another example of loss aversion - **changing feels riskier than staying the same.** **People perceive losses as less fair than missed gains, even if the outcomes are identical.** This affects how they judge pricing, wages, and policies. These fairness judgments are deeply influenced by how situations are framed.